Bhikkhunī Dhammadinnā
This is an edited version of an invited paper (with the pre-assigned title “Building hope as a contribution to the common good: An urgent co-responsibility in the spirit of universal fraternity. A Buddhist position”) read at the conference “Buddhists, Christians, Hindus, Jains and Sikhs: In dialogue and collaboration to renew and to re-ignite hope in our times,” which was held at the Pontifical Gregorian University, Rome, on June 4th, 2025, organized by the Dicastery for Interreligious Dialogue in collaboration with the Centre for Interreligious Studies of the Pontifical Gregorian University, the Unione Induista Italiana, the Unione Buddhista Italiana, the Institute of Jainology and the Sikhi Sewa Society.
Read the original article here

“Hope” may be regarded as a cornerstone of spiritual and existential resilience or valorised as a virtue tied to divine promise and eschatological fulfilment; within modern secular discourse, it functions as a psychological resource against despair and as a motivational force for social change. But what of the Buddhist position (or of a Buddhist position) on hope, with Buddhism being often represented as a tradition oriented solely toward renunciation, detachment, and the cessation of desire. This appears to be implicitly antithetical to the very thrust of the intentional act of reaching toward the future, which is the fundamental posture of “hoping,” at least in the common-sense understanding of the term? Can we speak meaningfully of hope within such a framework? And, if so, what form might Buddhist “hope” take? Is it sufficient to identify some equivalent of this concept in the doctrinal Buddhist lexicon, or is a more articulated analysis necessary of how this construct is (or is not) articulated within the Buddhist teachings?
I preface what follows by saying that any attempt at offering a sufficiently nuanced Buddhist position on “hope” in a way that does justice to the ways in which this construct takes shape in the many text- and religio-historical layers of the Buddhist traditions—in the plural—would be unfeasible of course in the present occasion. Thus, to address this question, I turn to the early Buddhist discourses that constitute the foundation for all subsequent developments in Buddhist thought and soteriology that inform the diverse Buddhist living traditions.
In fact, the Indic term “hope” (āsā and āśā respectively in Pali and Sanskrit, two of the main scriptural languages of the early Buddhist textual tradition) appears rarely in the early texts and, when it does, may be marked by ambivalence. For instance, the sage is described as having gone “beyond hope and despair” (Sn 4.3). This dual transcendence may suggest nihilistic abandonment or emotional austerity. Yet, the goal of Buddhist practice is not emotional numbness but liberative clarity. The Buddha’s “rejection of hope” is not the rejection of possibility, but of the mental proliferation (Pali papañca, Sanskrit prapañca)—the delusional hypertrophy of the ego—that attaches to outcomes and thereby binds one to suffering. Moreover, it unavoidably reifies the other by way of confining her or him to the function of fulfilment of one’s own needs.
Being hopeful, in this sense, becomes suspect not in its aspiration but in its entanglement with craving, that is, the thirst for experience and the thirst for the annihilation of experience (Pali taṇhā, Sanskrit tṛṣṇā). Such a form of “expectation” is among the proliferations that obscure the immediacy of the Dharma, i.e., reality and epistemic alignment with reality. Hope for future salvation, for attainment, or for relief by means of controlling existence in the form of its continuation or else its suppression—even subtly—can become a veiled clinging to reified self-view: to pin one’s hope on some state of becoming, an otherwiseness, is to be caught again in the vortex of saṃsāra, and it is the expression of a conflictual stance towards existence itself. At the same time, personal transformation and facilitation of external change are the sole intentional choices and actions—at the physical, verbal and mental level—that resolve the impasse of such a conflicted position and real-ise, make change real.
Clearly, this implicit critique of (what is seen as misguided) hope is far from being a doctrine of resignation. Throughout the early Buddhist scriptures, we encounter a different kind of orientation—a trust in the possibility of transformation. Hope is recast as a calm assurance in the intrinsic value of the path itself. And now I am looking at how this construct is articulated in the early teachings, attempting to make at least some of its dimensions explicit. The Buddha is on record as having stated that he would not have established a form of life designed to actualise the path to emancipation from all that is unwholesome (to which I return below) had he not seen such an emancipation as possible. In a sense, the whole decision on the part of the Buddha to share with others a path to the end of their own suffering and the historical establishment of the Buddhist community with its monastic and lay members is a hopeful gesture rooted in the conviction that change is possible.
Buddhist hope is epistemically and soteriologically rooted in the realization of awakening, that is, emancipation from all distortions and conceits. Discernment between the wholesome (pali kusala, sanscrito kuśala) and the unwholesome (pali akusala, sanscrito akuśala), and the decision to embrace the wholesome, form the capacity for moral life. The strong interest in a transformative moral psychology centred on subjective experience characterizes Buddhist moral discourse as a moral phenomenology, where the training in ethics and the training in mindfulness incrementally reinforce each other.
Ethics is not compartmentalized away from other domains of existence because the Buddhist mapping is informed by an integrated vision of the affective, cognitive, aesthetic, ethical, etc. terrains of experience. This approach is a consequence of the Buddha’s unbiased knowledge of the principles of construction of subjectivity he affirms to have attained through first-person realization of the truth of awakening (Nibbāna or Nirvāṇa respectively in Pali and Sanskrit). As a result, ethics is primarily oriented toward the final deliverance of the heart-mind (Pali and Sanskrit citta) from defilements and ignorance, free from any potential for deception or falsehood. Such interrelatedness of the teachings on ethics and liberation finds paradigmatic expression in a concatenated definition of virtue, concentration, and wisdom, stipulating that the proper development of each is a condition for that of the subsequent quality, and when wisdom is properly developed the mind-heart becomes liberated.
As the paramount epistemic and soteriological value, awakening also serves as the highest ethical value, reckoned as resulting in the remainderless cessation of what is unwholesome. The entire trajectory of ethics is built upon this foundational distinction between what is “wholesome” arising from the three roots of non-greed, non-anger, and non-delusion, and what is “unwholesome”, arising from the three roots of greed, anger, and delusion. Ethics is embedded in the pedagogical scheme of the so-called four noble truths. These are informed by the Buddha”s own awakening, which constitutes their source and their foundation. In the recognition that there exists (or there occurs) the experience dukkha (Pali; Sanskrit duḥkha) and that suffering is present in the way I construct the world of self and other (first truth), they affirm the universality of the possibility of the end emancipation from its cause, craving (third and second truth) through an intentional path of cultivation (fourth truth).
Notably, dukkha can at times involve “suffering” and even outright “pain”; but dukkha is not in itself suffering or pain: it is that which is by its very nature unsatisfactory and constitutionally incapable of providing peace and contentment. Even hedonically pleasant experiences and sublime states of mind such as the most profound meditative absorptions are marked by dukkha without causing any suffering or pain at all. Moreover, the existential unease that is dukkha is also distinct from psychopathological discomfort in the strict sense.
This points to the fact that the specifically Buddhist understanding of “hope” that emerges from the early discourses is one not rooted in projection or craving, but rather in a gradual alignment with the reality of life as it is and in an unshakable confidence in the path of existential transformation at the internal as well as interpersonal level. This is in turn a call for an attitude that does not rush to resolution. Hope begins with the acknowledgment and contemplation of dukkha: acceptance of what is not satisfactory, at times painful, without surrender to despair.
The capacity to offer hope to oneself and to others lies in the ability to co-inhabit the world of suffering together, while coexisting with the realistic possibility of change that is intrinsic to the very nature of reality, which is made up of causes and conditions rather than immutable essences. As a matter of fact, the principle of conditionality of mental states, of inner life as well as relational life, grounds agency and ethical ownership. Agency and ethical ownership are in this way the heart of Buddhist hope.
This brings us back to the epistemic status of hope in early Buddhism. In this framework, what can be known is prioritized over what can be hoped for. In a sense, early Buddhist faith (Pali saddhā, Sanskrit śraddhā) is not a substitute for liberating knowledge, but a provisional confidence that supports inquiry. It occupies a provisional epistemic space: not yet knowing, but willing to proceed based on tested principles. The fully awakened person is reckoned faithless (assaddha), having gone beyond the need for such a type of faith by dint of having attained liberating knowledge and irreversible ethical purification.
Buddhist hope—if we may still use that term—manifests as a justified, pragmatic confidence grounded in the law of conditionality and cause-and-effect. One does not believe blindly that awakening will come, nor does one despair if it is not immediately present. Instead, one cultivates a trust in the path because it has yielded fruits, not only for others but in one’s own life. In this way, hope in early Buddhism occupies a low-epistemic-risk, high-moral-value position. It is epistemically cautious but existentially generative.
I would suggest that this may be best appreciated as a form of epistemic humility. In contrast to dogmatic certainty about metaphysical truths or blind optimism about the future, the Buddhist practitioner recognizes the limitations of her or his finitude and epistemic faults. In a soteriologically-informed epistemology and epistemologically-informed soteriology, this is quite crucial. Hope, therefore, becomes grounded not in belief about the future, but in the moment-to-moment verification that the mind can be trained, defilements weakened, and suffering reduced. This is hope through insight. This is hope through deconstructing the self-referentiality and self-conceit that always accompany craving for the two proverbial two extremes of further becoming or else for its suppression.
This subtle, sober orientation reflects an “existential confidence”: a confidence not in outcomes, but in process. It is worth emphasizing that this quality is not static. It is cultivated, strengthened, and deepened through contact with the Dharma (i.e., access to the Buddha”s teachings), the example of more advanced disciples of the Buddha, and one”s own experience. As such, it serves not only as a psychological foundation, but also as an epistemic bridge between ignorance and wisdom. It permits movement and scope for effective action without requiring final supramundane knowledge. It keeps the practitioner in relationship with the path even when first-person certainty is unavailable. In that way, whilst honouring and foregrounding the subject’s epistemic and ethical agency, it does away with any form of glorification of experiential subjectivity as the main or sole valid existential terrain and compass.
This becomes especially poignant in the context of death and impermanence. Buddha offers a simile: a person is swept away by a great river and grasps at grasses on the bank. Let go, the Buddha enjoins, let go of the past, the future, and the present. With a heart freed of clinging, cross to the far shore (SN 3.25). This is not hope as projection but hope as release. It is a movement toward awakening not through possessing a secure future, but through becoming fully present to the present, with full responsibility. Mental proliferation generates an illusory world of duality, where hope and fear arise as oscillating responses to imagined scenarios (MN 18). To see through proliferation is to disarm both hope and fear—not through indifference, but through wisdom. The relinquishing of hope, paradoxically, opens the door to a deeper freedom: one no longer lives in reference to projected outcomes, but in the freedom of presence. Mindfulness becomes an expression of a non-attached hope—each moment of lucid attention affirming the potential for awakening. Not through fantasy or metaphysical promise, but through sustained intimacy with reality. From this standpoint, the Buddhist approach to hope is not escapist but deeply grounded.
In a world marked by ecological collapse, economic inequity, and widespread violence, this pragmatic, epistemically modest form of hope is crucial. It affirms human agency, ethical clarity, and the real possibility of transformation, without requiring metaphysical commitments that may falter under scrutiny or else might be unwarranted impositions on others. There is no salvation as an external gift, but there is freedom as an internal unfolding and the attendant relational authenticity. And that unfolding can be trusted.
Notably, hope is not merely as a state of mind but a phenomenon with embodied and relational and interpersonal implications at the same time when it arises in the space of care. Here the Buddhist practitioner attends to the dukkha or the suffering of another without feeling the urgent need to eliminate it (this stance must be understood delicately in its depth; obviously, saying that a Buddhist does not seek to immediately resolve pain or suffering, their own and/or that of others”, can lead to misunderstandings, as it may evoke views such as the belief that pain is the result of karma and therefore should not be alleviated, or it may recall notions of purification or atonement through suffering). Hope, in this light, is co-constituted: it exists where the possibility of healing is made present not through guarantee, but through presence itself. It does not aim at a hasty, pre-emptive, externally administered closure, resolution, and the erasure of dukkha (or of suffering) without first listening by approaching the other and recognizing the full legitimacy of their present condition.
Here hope is more deeply linked to cura (care) than to cure—it emerges not when we assert that things will improve, but when we remain faithfully present to what is, especially in moments where improvement cannot be promised. In this context, hope takes on a temporal vulnerability: it is the openness to a future not yet determined, without demanding that the future conform to our expectations.
Through applied contemplative practice, I come to apprehend experientially a fundamental homogeneity between the constitution of my embodied experience and that of the other, of others. There is real, lived continuity, and there is commonality in this experience of the way I construct my experience of my own embodiment and the way others construct their own experiences of their own embodiment. And this is our meeting point. This is where we already meet. This is where communion and fraternity arise, namely, from a fundamental insight into the commonality of the embodied predicament rather than, say, appealing to a normative noble intention or even a religious ideology. The quality of presence (i.e., mindfulness) builds or re-builds lives that no longer need attachment.
In closing, I would like to offer the image of the lotus to illustrate the only apparently contradictory Buddhist position on hope-without-hope. The lotus does not hope to bloom; it simply grows in accordance with causes and conditions. Likewise, the person who cultivates ethics, inner collectedness and wisdom does not hope in the conventional sense. Her or his is hope without grasping, responsible and co-responsible—and, from a Buddhist perspective, it may well be the most truthful hope of all.
Thanks are due to Elena Trusel and Boris Zobel for their comments on a draft of this text.

Abbreviations
MN Majjhima-nikāya
Sn Sutta-nipāta
SN Saṃyutta-nikāya
